Page images
PDF
EPUB

seem, has not yet been told, The very savages have families, and provide for them with no little care. We must sink below the Patagonian, who performs this duty, to find either the character or the circumstances of those who do not. The savages, in many instances at least, are chaste; in all, are the subjects of natural affection; and feel strong attachments to their friends and their nation. These means of comfort, these last hopes of virtue, the philosopher whom I have mentioned proposes to destroy. In their stead he leaves nothing but the fierce and brutal passions of men sanctioned by the voice of philosophy, and legalized by the decrees of legislation. These passions and appetites wholly unrestrained, because thus legalized and sanctioned, would originate, direct, and control all the future conduct of men, What these passions would dictate, we know from what they have always dictated. What they would accomplish, we know from what, when let loose, they have heretofore accomplished. If any man is at a loss on this subject, he may find a faint image of what he seeks, in a den of thieves or a horde of banditti. To complete the picture, let him cast his eye onward to a lair of wild beasts, and a stye of swine. With all these objects in view, he would find a faint image of the degraded, ferocious, guilty, suffering state of this miserable world, accomplished by these Godwinian means of perfection. Virtue itself therefore, according to the scheme of this writer, would become the cause of exterminating all virtue from the breast of man, as well as of rooting all enjoyment out of the present world.

3. We have here a specimen of the success with which human philosophy directs the moral concerns of mankind.

The Scriptures have required us to love our neighbour as ourselves;' and have directed the application of this principle in such a manner as to give it its utmost efficacy, and to produce by means of it the greatest mass of human good. "God," says Dryden, "never made his work for man to mend." A philosopher, laying hold on this principle, and understanding it only in the gross, has undertaken to direct its application anew, and in a manner better suited to his own feelings. The consequence (as we have seen) is, the gold is changed into dross in a moment, the food into poison. That, which as the Scriptures taught and directed it, nay, that which

6

[ocr errors]

left to itself, to its own inherent tendencies, would produce nothing but happiness, would, as taught by this infidel philosopher, destroy all the good of man. The benevolence of the Scriptures would make heaven; that of Godwin would produce a hell. Such are the effects of human philosophy when, resisting the ordinance of God, and forgetting that the foolishness of God is wiser than men,' she boldly interferes with the system of his truth and providence. The scene before her is as the garden of Eden,' filled with life, beauty, and happiness; brilliant and glorious as is the heaven-devised landscape, and fraught as Paradise with every thing good for food,' or pleasant to the eye.' She is still unsatisfied with her allotted condition, and with the scheme of her destined enjoyment. Not desirous of becoming, but conscious of having already become, as gods, knowing good and evil,' she puts forth her presumptuous hand, and, resolved to add to her stock of blessings such as she knows to be prohibited, seizes in an evil hour the forbidden good. How wonderful, how distressing the change! In a moment the fascinating scene has vanished; and Paradise, with all its beauty, happiness, and splendour, has fled for ever. Where bloomed the tree of life, and flowed the waters of immortality, nothing remains but a world of thorns and briars,' an immeasurable waste of sorrow and death.

[ocr errors]
[ocr errors][ocr errors]

SERMON LXXX.

REGENERATION.

ITS ATTENDANTS.

CONSISTENCY OF BENEVOLENCE WITH SEEKING SALVATION. &M

WHO WILL RENDER TO EVERY MAN ACCORDING TO HIS Deeds: ΤΟ THEM, WHO BY PATIENT CONTINUANCE IN WELL-DOING SEEK FOR GLORY, AND HONOUR, AND IMMORTALITY, ETERNAL LIFE.

ROMANS 11. 6, 7.

IN the last Discourse I considered one favourite objection against the doctrine of disinterested love: viz. “If we are required to love others as ourselves, we ought to do as much for them as for ourselves: particularly, we ought to make the same provision for them and their families, which we are bound to make for ourselves and our families."

This objection, I endeavoured to show, is so far from being grounded in truth, or from being a general consequence from the doctrine of disinterested love, that, as the world is constituted, love dictates the contrary conduct. Disinterested love prompts those who possess it to produce the greatest mass of happiness in their power. But the scheme proposed, instead of producing more happiness, would destroy that which now exists, and subvert whatever is desirable in the present state of things.

In this Discourse I propose to consider another plausible

SER. LXXX.

CONSISTENCY OF BENEVOLENCE, ETC.

141

objection against this doctrine, viz. that "we are commanded to seek eternal life, as the proper reward of our faith and obedience; and that this reward is promised to those who believe and obey, by God himself. This command, and this promise, (it is alleged) being given by God himself, cannot be denied to be right. That we ought, therefore, to seek for everlasting life, must of course be admitted. But this, (it is asserted) is aiming at a reward; is a conduct, springing from self-love; and is not disinterested. It follows then," say the objectors, "either that disinterested love is not required in the Scriptures; or that the requisitions of the Scriptures are inconsistent with each other." This objection, it will be observed, lies in the conclusion only. The premises are just and true. If the conclusion follows, I will give up the doctrine.

Lord Shaftesbury formerly advanced, with great labour and parade, a similar doctrine, but for a very different purpose. He maintained that disinterestedness is virtue, and the only virtue. At the same time he denied that it could consist with any hope of reward, or any fear of punishment. These, he declared, made virtue mercenary, mean, and selfish. True virtue, according to his scheme, consists wholly in doing good for the sake of that good; for the pleasure found in the good done, considered by itself, and wholly unconnected with any consequences; without any regard to advantages arising from it, or to disadvantages springing from the contrary conduct.

This celebrated writer, it is true, teaches elsewhere the opposite doctrine; and asserts, that "all the obligation to be virtuous arises from its advantages, and from the disadvantages attendant upon vice; and that such advantages are a great security and support to virtue." These, and other things of the like nature, he declares with no less confidence than the former opinions. It would be easy therefore to refute him by his own declarations. But this, though it might answer the purposes of mere controversy, would not satisfy a Christian audience. Were infidels required to be consistent with themselves, they never would appear in the field of debate.

The conclusion which Lord Shaftesbury drew from his principle was, that "the Scriptures, so far as they have influence, annibilate, by threatenings and promises, all virtue."

Hence he inferred, and, as it would seem, in his own view irresistibly, that "the Scriptures cannot be the word of God." Both these views of this interesting subject are, I apprehend, radically erroneous, and founded in false and imperfect conceptions of disinterested love.

1

In the text it is declared that 'to those who by patient continuance in well doing seek for glory, honour, and immortality, God will render,' as a reward, 'eternal life.' To seek for glory, honour, and immortality, therefore, is in a high degree pleasing to God; and must of course be truly and eminently virtuous conduct. If this conduct consists with disinterestedness, and arises from it, it must be acknowledged, on the one hand, that disinterestedness is not impeached by the objection already recited; and, on the other, that the Scriptures, while they require and encourage us to seek eternal life, do not render virtue mercenary, nor destroy, nor in any degree lessen, either virtue itself, or the obligations to virtue.

Before I enter upon the direct proof of this doctrine, it ought to be remarked that the scheme of Lord Shaftesbury confutes itself. His favourite doctrine is, that virtue consists wholly in doing good for its own sake, without any regard to any advantage which may follow from it, or to any disadvantage which may arise from a contrary conduct; such regard being in his view a destruction of virtue. Now let me ask, What is the difference between doing good for the sake of the pleasure attending it, and doing good for the sake of the pleasure following it? According to Lord Shaftesbury, virtue consists in doing good for the sake of the pleasure which it furnishes. Suppose then the virtuous action to be done now, and the pleasure furnished by it to be enjoyed an hour hence, or to-morrow. Would it be in any sense more mercenary to do the action for the sake of enjoying this pleasure an hour hence, or to-morrow, supposing the pleasure to be the same, than for the sake of enjoying it at the time when the action is done? The pleasure, according to the supposition, is the same in kind and degree. Can it then be any more or less virtuous to be thus influenced by a pleasure which will exist an hour hence, or to-morrow, than by the same pleasure existing at the present moment?

The truth in this case undoubtedly is, that it is neither

« PreviousContinue »